Tip:
Highlight text to annotate it
X
Prof: So in Monday's lecture we let something slip by
all of us without comment that we probably should not have let
slip by, and it's something I want to
focus on today.
That is when we spelled out Mill's harm principle I said,
"Is everybody sure they know what it means?"
Never mind whether you agree with it or not,
but whether you're sure that you understand what he is
saying, and we all agreed that at least
it was clear.
In fact, though, it's ambiguous,
and the highlighted phrase is the ambiguity I want to focus
on.
At the end of that long paragraph I read you when Mill
is saying, "If you think something's
bad for somebody or that they shouldn't do it,"
remember I gave you an example of going to law school when I
don't think it's good for you.
Mill says, "Those may be good reasons for remonstrating
with him, or reasoning with him,
or persuading him, or entreating him,
but not for compelling him or visiting him with any evil in
case he decides to do otherwise.
To justify that (I need to justify forcing somebody to do
something or prohibiting somebody from doing something)
the conduct from which it is desired to deter him must be
calculated to produce evil to someone else."
"Must be calculated to produce evil from someone
else."
And there are two issues raised by that phrase that I really
want us to focus on with laser-like intensity in today's
lecture.
The one is signaled by the passive voice in it,
"must be calculated."
Well, that obviously puts on the table, who does the
calculating, right?
And secondly, what does it mean,
calculated?
It could mean calculated as in intended.
"I didn't intend to harm you.
There was no calculation to harm you when I got
paralytically drunk behind the wheel of a car,
and then I don't even remember putting the keys in the wheel
and driving off.
I didn't intend to harm you," right?
Or is it a third party calculation?
Again, then we get to the question, by whom?
Who's going to decide?
Who's going to do the calculating?
So what does calculated actually mean,
and who is it that's going to do the calculating?
Those are the things we're going to zero in on today.
And I thought the best way into it was to consider some
examples.
And one I left you with on Monday was, what about
prostitution?
This is what is sometimes referred to as a so-called
victimless crime.
After all, the transaction between a *** and a
client is a Pareto superior transaction, right?
It's a voluntary market transaction.
They wouldn't do it if it didn't make both people better
off.
So should we just say from Mill's point of view,
"There's no harm here; it truly is a victimless crime
and we shouldn't make things criminal if they are
victimless?"
How many people think that makes sense?
About half.
Who thinks it doesn't make sense?
Nobody?
Yeah. Okay, so why?
Why doesn't it make sense, somebody who thinks it doesn't
make sense?
Over here?
Why were you thinking it didn't make sense?
Student: Even though it's victimless I think harming
yourself has some sort of implications,
I think.
Prof: So it's the *** harming herself?
Student: Sort of.
I think there are some moral implications in there that must
be dealt with.
Prof: Like what?
What kinds of implications?
Student: Besides just harming--okay,
let me take that back, harming yourself.
It might harm society in the sense that it brings down
society's moral standards, I guess.
Prof: Okay, it might harm society.
Mill's very clear that he wants to reject the idea that there
are social rights, so he wouldn't accept that,
but I don't think you should give up so quickly.
Is there some other way of articulating what you have in
mind there when you say harm society?
What do you mean?
If you unpack what does it mean when you say,
"harm society?"
It's tricky.
Anyone else want to have a go?
Yeah, right behind you.
Student: I guess it poses a negative externality on
society, and therefore...
Prof: Okay, and what is the negative
externality?
Student: Well, I guess in the case of
prostitution it could be the objectification of women in this
case.
Prof: Objectification of women, okay.
How would we say that's a harm to society?
Maybe it would be--again, Mill's going to reject the idea
that society has a right not to be harmed.
How can it play out in a way that doesn't involve making that
claim that society...?
Student: Well, I guess you could say it poses
a negative externality on the individuals in the society by,
I guess...
Prof: On women.
Student: Yeah.
Prof: On women.
It poses a negative externality on women.
It reinforces the set of stereotypes and so on.
Okay, so that might be one way in which prostitution causes
harm.
Any other ways? Yes, sir?
Student: It could also be said that it has a negative
externality because it undermines family values.
Prof: It undermines family values.
Student: Which would then, in turn,
hurt children and the future generations.
Prof: And that would, in turn, hurt children.
Yeah?
Student: Well, I think it's difficult also to
disconnect prostitution from this sort of theoretical model
from the actual model of prostitution.
I think when we put pimps, and *** slavery,
and that sort of thing in the picture then the harm becomes
far more real, and it's questionable whether
people are voluntarily participating in these
transactions to begin with.
Prof: Okay, so if you're a really
hardboiled Millian libertarian I think slavery's not an issue.
Slaves are taken by force, but selling yourself into
indentured servitude is not obviously something--
would Mill say you should be allowed to do that?
It's your choice.
It's tricky because you're really giving up your autonomy.
You'll see in politics, we confront later in the
course, what do you do with an election
where a party runs, as in Algeria in 1991 saying,
"If elected we are going to abolish democracy,"
and they get elected.
In that case the Algerian military stepped in.
If somebody says, "I'm going to sell myself
into servitude," it's a voluntary act,
should we save them from themselves?
That's a very tricky one, but let's set those ones aside.
And I think there would be similar issues with suicide for
Mill.
Should you be allowed to stop people committing suicide?
Those are very hard.
I think they're separate, though, from these issues about
what we're calling externalities.
People are saying, "Of course there are
harmful effects of prostitution.
It harms women.
It undermines certain kinds of moral codes.
What would Mill say in response to that?
Yeah?
Student: Well, I think for Mill it really
depends on the context of an act.
So you can be drunk at home, but you can't be a policeman
drunk on the job.
So if we look at prostitution if you're working as a free
agent, sure, you can engage in
prostitution, but if you're a father and
you're married then he should probably view that as something
not okay.
So it really matters for him what the context is of a certain
transaction.
Prof: Okay, I think that's right,
and you could imagine a more refined version of the harm
principle that tried to incorporate that.
I gave the example last time; I think I said,
"Mill would presumably be completely comfortable without
outlawing drunk driving and punishing that activity,
but not punishing drinking."
So presumably the principle would be some version of
"interfere with human conduct as little as possible to
prevent harm," right?
So it's killing a gnat with a sledgehammer to outlaw drinking
just because some people drive drunk.
I think that's fair enough.
But I think some of the people who were saying allowing
prostitution has bigger negative externalities wouldn't give up
that quickly.
Anyone who thinks we shouldn't give up that quickly,
that there's something else here?
Nobody?
Maybe they would give up that quickly.
Okay, we'll leave that aside for a minute and come back to
it.
So if you're now bearing this in mind go back and reread On
Liberty.
I think what you'll come away with is it's actually quite
confusing just what Mill means by harm.
Because some harms, he wants to say,
are trivial harms, so the harm you suffer through
not getting a place in college in a competitive exam,
right?
He's not going to allow that harm ultimately to be
dispositive.
He's going to allow that to be outweighed by the benefits to
society of competitive meritocracy.
And remember our free trade discussion last time.
So some harms are more significant than other harms and
some harms are outweighed by utilitarian benefits.
It seems like, some of the time,
if Mill's saying, "Prohibition shouldn't be
allowed," he's saying essentially,
"Unless I intend to do you some harm.
You might find it offensive that I sit around drinking all
day, but it's none of your business.
You might have family values which say that if there are
people out there who are prostitutes, it undermines the
family.
That's your family value, thank you very much.
It's not my family value," right?
So you could take that view.
And after all, if you think about the debate
we've had in this country about gay marriage over the past
decade or so, that's exactly the claim and
the counterclaim, right?
Some people say, "There's no reason in the
world that gay people should be prevented from getting married.
They're not hurting anybody else."
And then people say, "Well, that undermines
traditional family values," right?
And the people who support gay marriage say,
"Well, so what?
Those are your traditional family values,
but they're not our traditional family values,
and why should yours...."
This is, after all, what Mill says,
the tyranny of majority opinion.
So what? Right?
This is supposed to protect individual freedom against it,
so one person's traditional family values is another
person's tyranny of majority opinion.
How are you going to resolve that?
What mechanisms does Mill have to resolve that?
And I think you could read On Liberty
with a fine-tooth comb and not come up with one,
and so you could say, "Well, so much the worse
for Mill.
We thought we had this wonderful rights-utility
synthesis where all good things would go together.
We could respect individual freedoms,
and promote social utilitarian efficiency based on science all
at the same time, but actually it turns out to
all be resting on a hill of sand,
and the minute you walk on it you start sinking."
And I think this is a good time to go back to the point I made
to you right at the beginning of the course when I said you
shouldn't be expecting the silver bullet in this course.
You shouldn't be expecting to find the theory that answers all
your questions.
What instead you're going to find is particular insights that
you can pick up and put into your bag of tricks and move on
with.
Because I think it is, at the end of the day,
a good critique of Mill to say, "There is no single
definition of harm and there's no good account of who makes the
decisions about harm."
And so to that extent his claim at the beginning of On
Liberty that there's one simple principle and this is
what it is, fails.
Nonetheless, there are some important and
enduring insights here that I think we're not going to want to
let go of.
One is, when you think about all of the ways human beings
interact, and all of the things we do
that cause us to have the possibility of bumping into one
another, maybe it shouldn't be the case
that there is a single definition of harm because
different definitions of harm are relevant to different types
of situation.
This is a little like the point somebody here made that Mill
would be interested in the context.
If you think about physicians; we allow physicians to buy
malpractice insurance in case they kill you by mistake when
they're doing surgery, but we don't allow bank robbers
to buy malpractice insurance so that if they kill you by mistake
when they're robbing a bank they can get off.
That tells you right there, there must be different
conceptions of harm that operate in different circumstances.
And indeed, if you want to start thinking about it a little
bit more systematically, harm is treated very
differently in different situations.
Think about this continuum I've put up here.
Some kinds of harm are completely excluded.
You're not held responsible for them at all.
If you have a death penalty and legal execution of people,
of course you harm the person you execute.
Certain kinds of wartime killing, of course you harm the
person that you kill, but we allow it.
We don't count it as a relevant harm.
Then here, I'm going down this continuum, we say that the
intention to kill is very important in the criminal law.
Does anyone know what this term mens rea is in the
criminal law?
No reason you should, but somebody might.
If you're charging somebody with a criminal offense the
government has to prove beyond a reasonable doubt various
elements of the crime, that the person did it,
that in fact that the crime occurred and that there was
something called mens rea,
or criminal intent.
"Guilty mind," that's what it means.
And in the criminal law we make that one of the elements of the
crime.
That's why things like the insanity defense become so
contentious because the person claims,
"Well, because I didn't know what I was doing,
I didn't have mens rea.
My client didn't have mens rea.
He didn't know what he was doing so he's not guilty by
reason of insanity.
He's not guilty," okay?
Or if you think about--you might say,
"Well, we do imprison people for vehicular homicide
when they get drunk," and the person says,
"But I didn't intend to kill them.
I didn't know I was driving.
How can you can you say I intended?"
Interestingly there we come up with a doctrine in the legal
system which we call constructive intent.
And what is the doctrine of constructive intent?
It's basically we say, "Well,
any reasonable person would know that if drive down to a
bar, and you have no way to get
home, and you then drink ten beers you would be putting
yourself in the position where could harm someone.
So we're going to impute the intent to you even though you
didn't have it."
That's the doctrine of constructive intent.
That's using exactly that kind of situation,
so in the criminal law, to go back to Mill,
we'd say "calculated to produce evil in someone
else."
It's got to be calculated by the person committing the harm,
okay?
So, why is that, you might say.
Well, criminal actions are actions which bring moral
opprobrium on people.
We lock them up.
They're really things we don't want people to do,
and we want people to internalize the incentive not to
do them.
So it's about their intentional actions, and then we're
punishing them for those actions.
Therefore, when we put sanctions on them we want them
to know that they could have behaved otherwise,
and so we want the intent to be present,
so constructive intent is sort of like intent,
but not exactly.
What about negligence?
Negligence is even less like constructive intent.
So negligence is the doctrine that let's suppose you live in a
neighborhood where there are lots of children,
small children, and you put in a swimming pool.
And let's say the law requires that you fence in your swimming
pool, but you leave the fence open,
the gate open, and a child goes in and falls
into your pool and drowns.
The doctrine of negligence would say,
"Well, yes of course you didn't intend that the child
would drown, but you were negligent in
leaving the gate open, so we're going to hold you
responsible."
So it's a little less than constructive intent.
It's negligent.
Any reasonable person would know that you shouldn't leave
the gate open.
So you were negligent.
It's still a state of mind, but it's obviously not the same
thing as intending to kill the child.
And then we could go even further down the continuum and
say, "There are some situations
where we say, 'We don't care about your state
of mind at all.'" So if an adult has sex with a
14-year-old and walks in and says,
"Well, Your Honor, she said she was 20,
and I thought she was 20.
She looked 20," and perhaps that's true.
Perhaps all of those things were true, she said she was 20,
I thought she was 20 and she looked 20.
"We don't care," we say as a society.
We don't care.
That's the notion of statutory ***.
It's sometimes called strict liability.
We're going to hold you liable anyway.
And why do we do that?
Presumably to give people the incentive to make sure as to
find out.
So when we say, "If she was 14 it's
statutory ***, or if he was 14 and she was 20
it's statutory ***," there it is,
too bad.
We don't care what she said, and we don't care what you
believed at the time because we want to ensure that people have
the incentive to find it out correctly."
Or we could think of Good Samaritan laws.
This is the situation where you're walking along,
and you see somebody drowning in a lake,
and at very little cost to yourself,
you could pull them out, but you say,
"I'm late for class, never mind.
I didn't push her in the lake."
In many states we have good Samaritan laws,
which if it really was at no trivial cost to yourself you
could have done that, you can be prosecuted for
failing to assist somebody in need of your help,
okay?
So that's obviously a very capacious definition of harm.
I mean, after all, the fact that we're all sitting
here rather than doing relief work in Haiti right now means
presumably that some people are suffering,
perhaps even dying as a result of our failure to go to Haiti
right now.
So once you go over this line into treating omissions to help
as a form of harm, as we do with Good Samaritan
laws, where will it end, right?
So you can see from this that if you wanted one definition of
harm to cover all situations that obviously isn't going to
make any sense.
Nonetheless, if you think about this
continuum, where you fall on it has huge implications for how
you're going to run your society.
And more interestingly than that, I've given you a kind of
static picture now, but these things actually
change.
Think about the drug thalidomide.
Who knows what happened with thalidomide?
Yeah, what happened with thalidomide?
Student: It came out in the late '50s.
It was used to treat morning sickness and it turns out that
the racemate of the drug causes teratoma in children born to
women taking the drug.
And so it was basically a failure of the drug industry to
look into the effects of the different structures of drugs in
humans.
Prof: Correct.
That's a very good summary.
And what's interesting about thalidomide from our point of
view is that in developing this drug,
which was given for morning sickness,
the pharmaceutical companies didn't cut any corners.
They did all the clinical trails correctly.
They got the FDA approvals.
Everything was done by the book.
Nothing illicit was done, and at that time the general
standard in tort liability--who knows what tort means,
t-o-r-t?
Not t-o-r-t-e, we're not talking about
chocolate cake.
What's a tort?
Nobody knows what a tort is?
Tort just means harm, right?
So the general standard for tort liability was negligence,
and they weren't negligent.
They did it by the book.
They got all of the approvals.
They got the clinical trials.
The FDA approved the drug.
And it's a famous case because it was an instrument by which
the courts decided to say, "You know what?
We don't care.
We don't care."
They moved from negligence to strict liability.
"We don't care that you did it all right.
The fact is, there are all of these children
who were born with missing limbs, and you're going to pay.
You, the drug companies, are going to pay.
We're going to hold you strictly liable.
We're going to treat it like (the example I gave before)
statutory ***."
Now, you might say, "Well, why?
Why would you do that?"
And interestingly the move in American tort law from
negligence to strict liability, those of you who go on from
here to the Yale Law School will learn all about it because the
intellectual giant of the move from negligence to strict
liability was *** Calabresi, long time Dean of the Yale Law
School, and now a Federal Judge on the
Second Circuit.
He wrote a book called The Costs of Accidents.
And the main argument of The Costs of Accidents was--this
was actually about auto accidents.
It was essentially utilitarian in that Calabresi looked at what
had already stated in New Jersey at that time.
If people rear-end one another in cars you can say,
"Well, who was negligent here?"
Was it the driver in front, or was it the driver in the
back?
If it was the driver in the front,
why, "Oh, well, he stopped too
quickly," or something like that,
or the driver at the back says, "Well,
my brakes weren't working or the driver at the front's brake
lights weren't working."
You have an argument.
And they have their lawyer, and you have your lawyer,
and you duke it out, and somebody wins and somebody
loses.
New Jersey said, "It's not worth it.
It's a waste of court time.
It's a waste of everybody's time.
So we're going to make the law which says, in a rear-ending
situation, the driver at the back pays, always."
Kind of rough justice, sometimes maybe the brake
lights on the front car really weren't working.
"We don't care.
It's just not worth the State of New Jersey's time to invest
the institutional resources and all the rest of it to allow
people to litigate these things.
It just costs too much.
It's not worth it."
So *** Calabresi came up with a little algorithm in which he
said, "The standard should be to
minimize the cost of accidents plus the cost of their
avoidance."
So you figure out the cost of all the rear-ending,
right?
And then you figure out, well, if we allow people to sue
what's the cost of avoiding accidents that way,
whereas if we don't allow them to sue for negligence,
what's the cost that way?
It's cheaper.
It's more efficient.
And anyway, there are probably some good side benefits;
it gives the person at the back the right incentive to keep a
distance they can stop, right?
So we make a utilitarian judgment.
The game's not worth the candle for negligence.
That's one defense of it.
Coming back to the thalidomide, minimize the cost of accidents
and the cost of their avoidance.
What do we want as a society?
We want the drug companies to have the incentive to go the
extra mile to do even more research than they have to do as
required by the FDA, to buy the insurance because
perhaps they're the deepest pocket.
They have the resources to do the research and to buy the
insurance.
If you're a pregnant woman thinking about taking a morning
sickness pill or not taking it, you don't have the resources to
do extra research.
So we put the burden on the party who can most cheaply avoid
it.
Now, the drug companies are saying, "That's outrageous.
It's totally outrageous.
We didn't do anything wrong and you're punishing us."
Strict liability.
So we moved, and the example of thalidomide
is just the tip of an iceberg.
In the whole of tort law there's been this thirty or
forty-year move from a negligence standard to a strict
liability standard.
And a fascinating intellectual debate between Calabresi,
who's the champion of strict liability,
and Richard Posner, who you probably have read some
of his books, a Judge in the Chicago Circuit
who defends negligence as more efficient.
So it's a debate between utilitarians in that sense.
And if we had more time I'd have you read some of that
debate.
You might be convinced at the end of it that Posner wins
intellectually, but as a matter of the politics
of it, Calabresi wins.
That is to say American tort law has moved,
since the 1950s, away from negligence to strict
liability.
Let's think of another example.
In the 1950s in America, a husband could not be
prosecuted for raping his wife.
There was no such crime.
There was, in other words, a conclusive common law
presumption that there was no such crime.
Now you might say, why?
Well, there's a historical answer.
It went back to the suspension of the legal identity of the
woman during marriage.
Essentially, it goes back to the old
patriarchal laws.
The daughter was more or less the father's property and then
he gave his property to the son-in-law as the husband's
property.
So the woman didn't have a legal identity as a person
during marriage, and this is why she lost
control of her property, right?
And that was restored, ultimately, by the Married
Women's Property Acts that recreated women's property
rights over, say, inherited wealth or
whatever it was.
It didn't automatically become her husband's property.
But there was this hangover from the nineteenth century that
a woman couldn't be *** by her husband,
and not only *** but other things like assault.
So in other words, you could walk up to a woman
you were not married to on the street,
and punch her in the face, and get arrested for that,
and convicted of assault, but if you did it to your wife
there was no crime.
So then we have the women's movement.
We have a lot of feminist pressure and organization,
and so we now have gone to a world in which marital *** is a
felony in about forty-five of the states and the federal
system.
So it's gone from having a conclusive common law
presumption against it, to making it a felony,
and all the other things have gone as well,
so inter-spousal tort immunity is gone.
You can be prosecuted for assaulting--in other words,
marriage is no longer a bar to things that would be criminal
actions outside.
So we've had a huge change in the law there from one
definition of what counts as a relevant harm to a different
definition of what counts as a relevant harm.
In the first case it was an argument about efficiency,
and the second is a political movement.
The women's movement had this enormous impact on the
redefinition of what sorts of harms the state should take
seriously in marriage.
Let me give you a third example.
If you go into employment law, or housing law,
or education, the American courts have,
for many decades, at least since Brown versus
Board of Education was handed down by a unanimous Supreme
Court in 1954, they've been concerned with
trying to get rid of discrimination.
Discrimination's a kind of harm, right?
So the question is; what do you have to show?
What do you have to show to convince the court that you've
been harmed and there should be remedy?
What do you have to show?
And during the Warren Court it was somewhat like strict
liability.
The Warren Court, Earl Warren was appointed by
President Eisenhower in 1953.
Eisenhower thought he was appointing a conservative
Justice, but he turned out to be wrong.
Earl Warren was, perhaps, the most liberal Chief
Justice of the twentieth century.
And the court, under his leadership,
developed the idea that all you had to do was show there was a
pattern of discriminatory effects.
You didn't have to show that anybody intended to discriminate
against anyone.
So in the education area, separate but equal,
the court said is inherently unequal.
We're not saying that the White southerners are necessarily
prejudiced against Blacks, many of them were,
but we're not going to get to that question.
We're just saying separate but equal is inherently impossible.
It's an oxymoron.
You can't have it, and we're saying that without
reference to the intentions of school administrators or anybody
else.
In housing patterns you do these kinds of studies like Ian
Ayres and the Yale Law School here is well known for having
done.
When people with exactly the same objective characteristics,
same income, same employment history and so
on going for a mortgage it turns out that African Americans are
denied mortgages at a higher rate than non-African Americans.
You don't have to show that that mortgage officer was a
racist, or was intending.
You produce the statistics, you show people with these
objective characteristics who are African American get denied
and those with the same characteristics who are not
African Americans don't get denied.
It's a patter of discriminatory effects.
We don't have to get into something like mens rea
or whatever is going on in the bank mortgage officer's head.
So that was the standard also in employment discrimination and
many other areas of the law of discrimination under the Warren
Court.
All you had to show was a pattern of discriminatory
effects.
But the Warren Court was gradually replaced first by the
Burger Court, then the Rehnquist Court,
and now the Roberts Court, and in that conservative
evolution discrimination law has gone this way on the continuum.
Now you can't get a remedy unless you can show the
intention to discriminate on the part of some public official.
So let's say in zoning ordinances,
you've got to show that some public official actually tried
to do the zoning in such a way as to exclude Blacks from a
certain neighborhood, let's say, before you can get a
remedy.
So in employment, and housing,
and education, and all of these areas of
discrimination we've gone the other way as a society,
right?
We've gone from a very capacious standard which would
allow a remedy just from the objective indicators,
the patterns of discriminatory effects,
now we treat it more like the criminal law.
We say, "Unless you can show,
you can establish in court that there was some particular person
in that bank denying mortgages who intended to discriminate,
no remedy."
So it's much harder, of course, to get remedies.
So those are three examples.
Those are three examples, the thalidomide,
the marital ***, and the discrimination,
where you can see that there's enormous flux in our society as
to what counts as a relevant harm.
And if we had time, I strongly suspect if we had
time to have a debate in this room on those three topics it's
not like we would all agree as to whether in discrimination law
it should be patented as discriminatory effects or
intent.
We'd have differences of opinion about that that would
stem from our assumptions about the appropriate role of
government, how intrusive it should be and
so on.
Or probably there would be less disagreement today about the
martial *** than there would have been in the 1950s,
and I suspect intuitions would go all over the place about tort
liability and the thalidomide.
So what does that tell us?
And this is the second reason I think it's really instructive to
work through somebody like Mill even if, in the end,
Mill doesn't have the answer.
I think one of the lessons of this course, and you can see it
here very dramatically, is that it is impossible to get
rid of political disagreement.
It is impossible to reduce political choices to scientific
choices all the way down.
Science can play important roles in making political
choices, but it can't make them for us,
so that one of the big goals of the Enlightenment to come up
with scientific principles of politics is never going to be
perfectly realized.
That doesn't mean it can't be partially realized,
but it's never going to be perfectly realized.
You can't wring the politics out of politics.
There's no way to do it.
And so you will see when we come to read Marx and he talks
about his utopian communist society,
one of his one-liners is that, at the end of the day when we
finally have the true communist utopia,
"Politics will be replaced by administration,"
right?
That's a bumper sticker for saying we're going to wring the
politics out of politics.
Bentham, looking for the right objective utilitarian calculus,
right?
Mill wants to say, "Well, once the harm's
triggered we can do the cost-benefit analysis on
scientific principles."
We talked about that last time.
Never works.
It never works all the way down.
It doesn't mean to say that scientific thinking can't
condition our normative choices, but you go back and think
through these three examples that I've just given you these
are basically normative choices, right?
In the 1950s when this issue about marital *** came up,
a lot of things were said that are similar to what is said now
about gay marriage.
People said if the state starts prosecuting husbands we're going
to destroy the traditional family.
And people the women's movement said, "Great!
We're going to destroy this traditional family because men
shouldn't be allowed to *** women.
At least in this respect we won it," right?
So traditional values only takes you so far because the
harm principle is by definition, a critical principle for
looking at traditional values and saying,
"How much should we cater to them,
how much not," right?
So these are political choices.
The choice about thalidomide has huge distributive
consequences, huge, enormous.
You're going to say to pharmaceutical companies,
"You're going to be liable from now on for the harmful
effects of your drugs regardless of whether you got the FDA
approval."
It's a huge burden to put on them.
Notice what we could say.
We could say, "No, (as a famous
libertarian Judge Learned Hand said) in society losses must lie
where they fall."
What does that mean?
It basically means the women who had the thalidomide children
and the children themselves must internalize the loss,
or we could say, "We'll socialize the
risk."
We'll say, "In these kinds of situations when there was no
wrongdoing in the sense of cutting corners;
the government will bail them out."
Just like we did after 9/11, we created this huge fund and
paid compensation to the relatives of people who died in
9/11.
Many people die all the time in disasters where we don't do
that, but we could.
We could have massive social insurance for unexpected harms.
So the choice to say, "Losses must lie where
they fall," with Learned Hand,
or that we should socialize it by saying,
"Well, if you're born with a physical deformity,
obviously it's through no fault of your own,
but really you can't blame the manufacturer of thalidomide
either, so the state will pick it up.
We as a society will do it."
That's a different choice.
Or if you say, "No, we're going to make
thalidomide--the manufacturer internalizes this,"
that's a different choice.
My point here is it's always a choice.
It's always a choice.
We'll come to read a libertarian called Robert Nozick
later in the course, and one of his one-liners is
that, "The fundamental question of political theory is
whether or not there should be a state."
But we'll see that that's a bit like saying,
"The fundamental question of dental theory is whether or
not there should be teeth," because in fact everything
involves collective choices.
Even the collective choice to let the loss lie where it falls,
that is itself a collective choice.
So you can't wring the politics out of politics.
And at least one goal of the Enlightenment,
we're going to see, there's this idea of replacing
politics with science, or in Marx's formulation,
of politics being displaced by administration,
can never be perfectly realized.
And that's an important insight we get from thinking about
trying to apply Mill's harm principle.
Okay, see you on Monday.