Tip:
Highlight text to annotate it
X
Professor Steven Smith: I want to look at two sets of
issues. I want to in,
a way, conclude my interpretation,
my reading of the Second Treatise,
by focusing on the role of executive power in Locke's
theory of government, Locke's theory of the
constitutional state, particularly focusing on the
role of the executive, vis-a-vis the legislative
branch of government, and then I want to turn a
little more speculatively to thinking about Locke and the
American regime and the current state of political philosophy,
modern contemporary American political philosophy.
But let me start first by going back and sticking with the
Second Treatise by talking a little bit about the
role of legislative and executive power.
The last time, I think, I was concluding by
arguing that Locke doesn't endorse necessarily one
particular form of government from any other.
He is an advocate of what we have come to call limited
government, of constitutional government.
There is that important passage where he ridicules the Hobbesian
sovereign as a lion and tells us we did not enter into the social
compact to be devoured by lions. He says, the form of government
must be limited although he's relatively open or at least
non-committal, agnostic you might say,
as to what particular form that government may take.
One feature of this form of government that he thinks is
very important, is that it must in some sense
embody a separation of powers, powers must be made to check
one another, what he calls in the book the subordination of
powers. This is Locke's doctrine and
you will see it there. We often associate it with
Montesquieu or sometimes with the federalist authors but,
in fact, Locke himself is a strong advocate of what he calls
the subordination or separation of powers,
not exactly the same as we'll see between our understanding of
executive legislative and judicial,
but nevertheless a separation nonetheless.
However, in the first instance, Locke emphasizes and in fact he
continually affirms nevertheless the primacy of legislative
authority. In England, in the England at
his time and even today, that means a doctrine of what
is called parliamentary supremacy but he says that the
first and fundamental positive law of all constitutions is in
establishing that of the legislative power.
The first act, after the completion of the
social contract, he says, is establishing the
legislative power. It is the lawmaking authority
of government that is supreme, he wishes to emphasize.
This seems to push Locke, you might, say more in the
small ‘d' democratic direction.
It is not so much executive power, the power of a prince,
but rather the legislature, the parliament that is supreme.
There is nothing more important, in Locke's theory of
constitutional government, than the existence of what he
continually refers to as settled or known laws,
settled laws that serve against arbitrary rule.
In many ways, the purpose of government for
Locke is much less to offset the dangers of returning to an
anarchic state of nature as it was for Hobbes than to prevent
the possibility of the emergence of tyrannical or despotic power,
tyrannical or despotic sovereign, and of course,
Locke's writing is very much bound up with the big and major
constitutional crisis of his time leading to the overthrow
and expulsion of a king, James II.
Yet in many ways, even though Locke is the great
advocate of legislative supremacy,
he obviously cannot and does not wish to dispense altogether
with the role of executive power.
He often treats the executive, whether that be in the form of
a prince, a monarch or perhaps even a body in a cabinet of
chief officers as it were. He treats them often simply as
if they were an agent of the legislative or of the
legislature. The purpose of the executive,
he sometimes seems to write, is merely that of carrying out
the will of the legislature. In Locke's language,
"the executive power is ministerial and subordinate to
the legislature," section 153, I believe.
The executive, again, on some aspects of
Locke's writing seems to be little more than a cipher in
comparison to the doctrine of legislative supremacy.
And yet, Locke here is not altogether consistent,
one has to say, because he understands in every
community there is a need for a distinctive branch of government
dealing with matters of war and peace.
Locke calls this the federative power.
Every community, he says, like Hobbes,
is to every other community what every individual is to
every other individual in the state of nature and a
distinctive federative or war-making power within the
government is necessary for dealing with matters of
international conflict, conflict between states.
And in a remarkable passage, Locke notes that this power,
he says, cannot be bound by antecedent standing positive
laws but it must be left to, quote, "the prudence and wisdom
of those whose hands it is in to be managed for the public good."
In other words, Locke seems to suggest that
this particular kind, this branch of government,
this federative branch which falls to some degree under the
executive, must have a certain latitude even apart from the law
that relies, he says, on the prudence and
wisdom of those whose hands it is in to manage it for the
public good. In other words,
matters of war and peace cannot be left to the legislature or to
standing laws, as he calls them,
alone but requires the intervention of strong leaders,
what he calls in an absolutely stunning passage god-like
princes, section--if you don't believe
me, section 166. Locke's reference here to
god-like princes seems to recall Machiavelli in many ways,
Machiavelli's talk of armed prophets.
It is necessary, in extreme situations,
for such princes to call on their prerogative power.
It is impossible, Locke writes,
to foresee and so by laws to provide for all the accidents
and necessities that may concern the public and that during,
in other words, contingencies or emergency
situations the executive must be empowered with this prerogative
power to act for the good of the community.
For this reason it seems, the executive is not simply a
tool or an agent of the legislature but he says,
again, must have the power to act according to discretion,
that is to say, according to his own discretion
for the public good without the prescription of law,
those are Locke's own words. How to balance his argument for
constitutional government and legislative supremacy with this
doctrine of prerogative power and what seems to be a kind of
power of what he calls in no uncertain term the god-like
princes and their need to exercise this power?
Locke's prerogative is, in many ways,
the result of simply the inability of law to foresee all
possible circumstances, all possible contingencies.
That's an argument that goes as far back as Aristotle,
we've seen. Our inability to make rules
that can apply to all possible events, makes it necessary to
leave some discretionary power in the hands of the executive to
act for the public safety. One of the examples that Locke
gives of the use of this power is in fact a domestic,
not an international issue, which is to say,
in the case of a fire in a city it is sometimes necessary,
he says, in his day for the fire department to tear down the
house of an innocent person to prevent the fire from spreading
to other houses. This is acting for the public
good of the community, even while in some ways it's
clearly a violation of rights of property and so on.
He understands this as a piece of prerogative power acting for
the public good. In fact, the example is not so
far fetched. Think today for example about
arguments we have today. Even in Connecticut,
there's a big argument going on about the right of what's called
"eminent domain," the right of the government to
absorb or to take over private properties whenever,
usually for things like schools or airports but also for general
improvement when it is thought it will enhance the public good.
There's a big debate going on right now out in New London and
in Brooklyn also with the argument about the creation of
some civic center, some sports arena that will
require the demolition of certain neighborhood houses.
And there's a big debate about this eminent domain.
What is that, but in a way Locke's example of
prerogative power, acting, doing something that is
somehow said to be for the public good but that represents
some kind of extra constitutional power?
But the question for Locke, as for any constitutional
lawyer, is what are the limits of this prerogative power?
What check, if any, is there on this power to
prevent their abuse? Well, Locke doesn't exactly say.
Yes. Right.
He doesn't exactly say. He raises this question to be
sure, of fundamental importance for constitutional government.
Does executive authority, he asked us,
extend to all things even or especially in times of war?
Think about the debates that are going on now about detainees
at Guantanamo or the issues of domestic spying when it comes to
issues of the war on terror. Are these examples of
prerogative power, that is to say,
the executive acting outside the limits or the bounds of
constitutional authority for the sake of protecting the public
good or are these examples of kind of political absolutism?
Is the invocation of this power, in some ways,
going down the slippery slope to despotism and absolutism?
I will leave it to you or your sections to try to discuss these
matters but Locke himself praises those who he calls the
wisest and best princes of England as being those who have
exercised the largest prerogative on behalf of the
public good. This is beginning to sound more
and more in respects like Machiavelli than the advocate
of, again, limited government. This power comes into play,
he says, especially during times of national crisis or
emergency when it is necessary to act for the public safety in
some ways. And again, this seems to have
special resonance for us today as we face issues like states of
emergency and states of exception.
There are in fact political theorists, one name comes to
mind, a twentieth-century German legal philosopher by the name of
Carl Schmitt who argued that the state of emergency or the
exceptional situation is the essence of politics and that the
person or body who has the power to declare the exception is none
other than the sovereign. So from Schmitt's point of view
you might say this idea of prerogative is a kind of extra
constitutional power that the statesman must of necessity
utilize when ordinary constitutional operations,
like the rule of law, prove to be inadequate.
But consider another example if you like, that prerogative
power, about prerogative powers that maybe granted by the
Constitution. Consider Lincoln's famous
suspension of habeas corpus during the Civil War.
Lincoln, interestingly, did not take this extraordinary
step by appealing to an extra-constitutional power that
obtains in times of crisis. Rather, Lincoln argued quite
forcefully that this sort of prerogative power is already
deeply embedded within the structure of constitutional
government. He cites the
Constitution when it came to the suspension of habeas
corpus. The Constitution writes,
"The privilege of the writ of habeas corpus shall not be
suspended unless when in cases of rebellion or invasion the
public safety requires it." In other words,
the Constitution itself seems to allow for this
extraordinary kind of action at least in cases of rebellion or
invasion when it says the public safety requires it.
The Constitution seems to embody within itself,
our constitution that is, this Lockean power of
prerogative that comes into effect or can be legitimately
exercised in times of rebellion or invasion.
Are we living in that kind of age now, not rebellion perhaps
but invasion? Well, think about that again.
Are these arguments applicable to our situation today,
in some sense, when it comes to debates about
the extent of executive power to embark on these extraordinary
measures? And yet at the same time,
Locke is aware clearly of the potential abuse of this kind of
prerogative. He asks, who will judge,
who can judge whether the discretion of the executive is
being used for the public safety or the public good or whether it
is simply a kind of usurpation of power?
In these moments of high constitutional crisis between
conflicting powers of government, in such cases,
Locke says there shall be no judge on earth.
He says the people have no other remedy in this but to
appeal to Heaven. This is in section 168.
How much is contained in that term "appeal to Heaven?"
What does Locke mean in terms of high constitutional crisis
when he says there is no judge on earth, the people must appeal
to Heaven? Does that mean they should fall
down on their knees and begin to pray, what they should do?
Unlikely. By an appeal to Heaven,
Locke means the people's right to dissolve their government.
He raises this question at the very end of the book.
When a conflict between the people or their representatives
and the executive becomes so great that the very conditions
of social trust have been dissolved,
who will be judge? And he answers emphatically:
the people will be judge. Locke affirms here a right of
revolution. An appeal to Heaven,
or what he calls an appeal to Heaven really refers to an
appeal to arms, to rebellion,
and the need to create a new social covenant.
Locke, you can see, is attempting to hold together
a belief in the sanctity of law and the necessity for
prerogative that may sometimes have to circumvent the rules of
law. Are these two doctrines
incompatible? I think in many respects or at
least in some respects they are. Can the prerogative power of
the executive be in a way constitutionalized so that it
does not threaten the liberty of its own citizens?
Locke alerts us to this timeless as well as this very
timely problem. One of the best sources for
thinking about many of these constitutional issues today,
regarding privacy rights and other kinds of citizen rights,
can be found in, I would say the last five
chapters or so of Locke's Second Treatise.
I can't think of a better source.
So in the end Locke's appeal to Heaven or Locke says the people
have an appeal to Heaven, that is to say an appeal to
arms, an appeal to revolution, suggests that at the end of the
day Locke was a revolutionary but I would say also a sort of
cautious and moderate one, if this is not a complete
contradiction in terms. I won't go through chapter 19,
the famous chapter on revolution in full,
to talk about the conditions under which he believed the
people can rightfully appeal to Heaven,
as it were, but Locke's doctrine of consent and
legislative supremacy, this should make him in many
ways a hero to Democrats, to radical Democrats.
His beliefs about limited government, the rights of
property should make him a hero to in some ways constitutional
conservatives and even libertarians.
In the end, I think Locke was neither or both.
Like all of the great thinkers in some ways,
he defines--he defies, excuse me,
simple classification but there is no doubt that Locke gave the
modern constitutional state its definitive form of expression.
And the problems of our state, the problems,
the legal, the constitutional and political problems that we
experience are very much problems rooted in the
philosophy of John Locke and are unthinkable without the
influence of Locke. So that takes me to a theme
that I want to talk about for a little while,
which is Locke's America, John Locke's America.
No one who reads Locke, even superficially,
and I would not accuse anyone here of being a superficial
reader, after all, but no one can fail
to be impressed by the harmony, in many ways,
between Locke's writings and those of the American Republic
that he helped to found. His conception of natural law,
rights, government by consent, the right to revolution and all
are all part of the cornerstone of our founding documents.
To some degree, as I've just been suggesting,
a judgment on America is very much a judgment on the
philosophy of Locke and vice versa.
In many ways, if anyone is,
I think Locke has the title to be considered America's
philosopher-king. So how should we think of Locke
after more or less three centuries of consistent Lockean
rule? How should we think of Locke?
For many years and for many people, even today,
the affinity, the affiliation between Locke
and America has been regarded in a largely although not wholly,
largely positive light. For many historians and
political theorists, our stability,
our system of limited government,
our market economy has been the result of a sort of broad
consensus over Lockean principles,
over Lockean first principles. But for many other readers of
American history, this relationship has been seen
as more problematic. In the 1950s,
a book written by a famous political theorist and
historian, named Louis Hartz, a book called The Liberal
Tradition in America, complained of America's,
what he called "irrational Lockeanism."
That was Hartz's line, that was Hartz's quote,
"irrational Lockeanism," by which he meant a kind of closed
commitment to Lockean principles and ideals that shut off all
other political alternatives and possibilities.
Hartz was someone very much interested in the question,
as many political theorists have been since,
why has there been no socialism in America, why did America not
evolve or develop along European lines with social democratic
parties and socialist parties like the English Labor Party and
other kinds of labor movements. And Hartz's argument was that
we were sort of arrested in this Lockean phase of development,
what he called our irrational Lockeanism that closed off in
many ways other principles. And for still other thinkers,
more or less on the left, Locke legitimized what was
called an ethic of what was called "possessive
individualism," particularly Locke's focus on
property and the rights of private property that focuses
entirely on market relations or puts the market values ahead of
all other things. And for still others,
in many ways more recently, thinkers of a more sort of
communitarian direction or bent, Locke's emphasis upon rights
and the protection, that government should protect
natural or certain unalienable rights,
suggests a purely or overly legalistic conception of
politics that has no language for talking about the common
good, the public good or other sort
of collective goods or benefit. So my point is that Locke's
influence has not been altogether accepted by everyone.
There has been much ground for criticism of this peculiar
affinity between Lockeanism and America.
But today, I would say that Locke's theory of liberalism or
Locke's theory of limited government,
constitutional government, is confronted by another
alternative that, in many ways,
has deep roots in the very tradition which Locke
himself---the very liberal tradition in many ways of which
Locke himself is the founder. And I am referring,
in particular, to a book that many of you will
read at some point in your Yale experience,
a book, widely read and widely acclaimed book by a recently
deceased political philosopher by the name of John Rawls who
wrote a book in 1973 called A Theory of Justice.
In many ways, Rawls' book was an attempt to
update the liberal theory of the state.
He invokes the idea of a state of nature, an original
condition, as he calls it, a theory of rights although he
does so in many ways through the techniques of contemporary
philosophy and game theory and Rawls' book is probably the
single most important contribution to Anglo-American
political philosophy in the last generation.
It is a book that situates itself within the liberal
tradition beginning with Locke, developed by people like
Immanuel Kant and John Stuart Mill in which Rawls himself
hoped to, in many ways,
bring to completion in his book.
A theory of justice, as he calls it,
stands or falls on its theory of rights from which all else is
derived. And what I want to do for a few
minutes is to contrast Rawls' general theory,
so powerful and influential today, from that of John
Locke's, the original founder of the liberal theory of the state,
and see how they have diverged. Consider the following
propositions, if you will.
Here is John Locke, section 27 of the Second
Treatise. "Every man has property in his
own person. This nobody has any right to
but himself and where there is property," he writes,
"there can be justice and injustice."
Here is John Rawls, one of the opening pages of his
Theory of Justice. "Each person," Rawls writes,
"possesses an inviolability founded on justice that even the
welfare of society as a whole cannot override.
For this reason," he continues, "justice denies that the loss
of freedom for some is made right by a greater good shared
to others." Okay.
So far, so good, in other words. Both of them present their
theories of justice as justified in terms of the liberal
principles of equality, freedom and the sanctity of the
individual and individual rights.
Both regard the purpose of government, in many ways,
as securing the conditions of justice as deriving from the
consent, or the informed consent,
of the governed but both it seems to me go on to differ
profoundly about the source of rights and therefore the role
that government has in securing the conditions of justice.
Let me explain a little bit more what I mean.
For Locke, going back to chapter 5 of the Second
Treatise, rights derived from a theory of
self-ownership. According to his view,
you will remember, everybody has a property in his
or her own person. That is to say,
no one has a claim on our bodies other than ourselves.
It is on the rock of self-ownership,
the fact that we have property in ourselves,
it is on the rock of self-ownership that Locke builds
his edifice of natural rights, justice, and limited government.
To put it in a slightly different way perhaps,
a person has an identity, what we might call today a
moral personality or an identity by the fact that we alone are
responsible for making ourselves.
He uses this metaphor of the work of the body and the labor
of our hands but we are literally the products of our
own making. We create ourselves through our
activity and our most characteristic activity is our
work. Locke's fundamental doctrine is
that the world is the product of our own free creativity,
not nature but the self, the individual is the source of
all value for Locke. It is this self,
the I, the me, the ego that is the unique
source of rights and the task of government is to secure the
conditions of our property in the broadest sense of the term,
namely, everything that is proper to us.
Now, using that as a sort of shorthand, contrast this to
Rawls' idea. Rawls adds to his idea of
justice something that he calls the "difference principle," the
DP as it's sometimes referred to in the literature on Rawls.
What is the difference principle?
This principle maintains that our natural endowments,
our talents, our abilities,
our family backgrounds, our history,
our unique histories, our place, so to speak,
in the social hierarchy, all of these things are from a
moral point of view something completely arbitrary.
None of these are ours in any strong sense of the term.
They do not belong to us but are the result of a more or less
kind of random or arbitrary genetic lottery or social
lottery of which I or you happen to be the unique beneficiaries.
The result of this, in other words,
is that no longer can I be regarded as the sole proprietor
of my assets or the unique recipient of the advantages or
disadvantages I may accrue from them.
Fortune, luck, Machiavellian fortuna,
in that way, is utterly arbitrary and therefore,
Rawls concludes, I should not be regarded as the
possessor but merely the recipient of what talents,
capacities and abilities that I may, again, purely arbitrarily
happen to possess. So what does that mean in terms
of social policy or theory of government?
The result of Rawls' difference principle and its fundamental
difference with that of John Locke could not be more striking
from this point of view. The Lockean theory of justice,
broadly speaking, supports a meritocracy
sometimes referred to as "equality of opportunity,"
that is, what a person does with his or her natural assets
belongs exclusively to them, the right to rise or fall
belongs exclusively to them. No one has the moral right to
interfere with the products of our labor, the products
of--which may also include not just in a primitive sense what
we do with our hands and bodies but what we do with our
intelligence and our natural endowments.
For Rawls, again, on the other hand,
our endowments are never really our own to begin with.
They are part of a common or collective possession to be
shared by society as a whole, the capacities of hard work,
ambition, intelligence and just good luck that,
for example, got you to a place like Yale,
on Rawls' account, do not really belong to you or
at least the fruits of those ambitions and intelligence and
good luck do not belong to you. Again they are somewhat
arbitrary as a result of upbringing and genetics.
They're not yours or mine, in any strong sense of the
term, but rather, a collective possession that
can be or should be the fruits of which distributed to society
as a whole. Consider the following passage
from Rawls. "The difference principle," he
writes, "represents in effect an agreement to regard the
distribution of natural talents as a common asset and to share
in the benefits of this distribution whatever it turns
out to be." Your intelligence or your drive
or your endowments are, again, what he calls a
collective asset. Think about that.
And it is this conception of common assets that underwrites
Rawls' theory of distributive justice and the welfare state,
just as Locke's theory of self-ownership justifies his
conception of limited government in the constitutional state.
According to Rawls, again, justice requires that
social arrangements be structured for the benefits of
the least advantaged in the genetic lottery of society.
His thought experiment that he calls "the original condition"
specifies that nobody would know in advance in this condition
what their particular endowment intellectually,
in many other ways, would be. Therefore, every individual
would, in contracting with the whole, would agree to share
equally in the benefits of this, as it were, genetic lottery.
So redistributing our common assets does not violate,
on Rawls' account, the sanctity of the individual
because again the fruits of our labor were never really ours to
begin with. Unlike Locke,
whose theory of self-ownership provides a moral justification
for the individual, for the self,
for our moral personality, Rawls' difference principle
maintains that we never again belong to ourselves at all.
We never really have ownership in ourselves but are always part
of a larger social "we," a social collective,
a collective consciousness whose common assets can be
redistributed for the benefit of the whole.
Locke and Rawls, the point I'm trying to make
is, they represent two radically different visions of the liberal
state, one broadly libertarian,
the other broadly welfarist, one emphasizing liberty,
the other emphasizing equality. Interestingly,
again, this transition, this evolution represents a
change which has gone on within in many ways the liberal
tradition itself. Unlike some of these other
critics, Rawls does not come to be claiming from a tradition
outside of liberalism but to be developing certain arguments
from within the liberal tradition and yet has moved in a
way clearly very different from its Lockean formulation.
Both of these views, again, they begin from common
premises but move in very different directions.
Locke's theory of self-ownership regards the
political community in largely negative terms as protecting our
antecedent individual selves and individual rights.
Rawls' theory of common assets regards the community in a far
more positive sense as taking an active role in reshaping and
redistributing the products of our individual endeavors for the
common interests. The question for you,
just like the question for any of us, is which of these two
views is more valid or which of the two strikes you as more
powerful or plausible? My own view,
and I loathe to editorialize, but my own view is far closer
to American theory, to Locke's theory,
which I think--than Rawls'. The Declaration of
Independence, the charter of American
liberty, states that each individual is endowed with
unalienable rights among which are life,
liberty, the pursuit of happiness.
The very indeterminacy of the last phrase, the pursuit of
happiness, with its emphasis upon the individual's right to
determine happiness for themselves,
suggests a form of government that allows for ample diversity
for our natural talents and abilities and although the
Declaration certainly intends that the establishment
of justice is one of the first tasks of government,
nowhere does it imply that this requires the wholesale
redistribution of our individual goods and assets.
And second, although Rawls is clearly attractive,
excuse me, Rawls is clearly attentive to the moral ills of
inequality and we will turn to that problem emphatically on
Wednesday when we look at Jean-Jacques Rousseau's Essay
on Inequality. There has never been a more
powerful, passionate and persuasive critic of the ills of
inequality than Jean-Jacques Rousseau but while Rawls is
certainly attentive to the moral ills of inequality,
he seems very naive about the mechanisms, the actual political
mechanisms, by which inequalities will be rectified.
Rawls wants government to work for the benefit of the least
advantaged but this will require the extensive and often
arbitrary use of judicial power to determine who has a right to
what, far in excess of the powers of
the court. The result would be,
I think if we follow Rawls' teachings to their letter,
the result would be not a class of philosopher-kings,
but rather a class of chief justices endowed with the power
to rearrange and redistribute our collective assets for the
sake of achieving the maximum degree of social equality.
It is no surprise that the warmest reception that Rawls'
writing gets today is in the schools of law,
is in the law schools where he has had an enormous influence on
shaping the education of the current and the next generation
of lawyers, judges and possibly chief
justices who may be looking to again, looking not to the
Constitution but to Rawls' theory of justice as a
litmus or a tool for bringing about social redistribution.
So, I leave you on that sobering note but a return to
Locke such as it is, even if such a return were
possible, is by no means a panacea to
what ails us. I am not suggesting for a
moment that Locke is some kind of cure all.
Some historians, let me just mention again,
Louis Hartz was but the most famous, treat America as a
nation uniquely built upon Lockean foundations.
America, he believed, remained something of a Lockean
remnant--a Lockean, yeah,
remnant, fossil in some ways, in a world increasingly
governed by more radical forms of modernity.
In fact, it has been our sort of stubborn Lockeanism that has,
in many ways, prevented the kinds of extreme
ideological polarization and conflict that one sees
throughout much of the nineteenth and twentieth
centuries. But Locke's effort to build a
kind of modern republican government on the low but solid
foundations of self-interest and self-ownership and the desire
for comfortable preservation could not help but generate its
own forms of dissatisfaction. Can a regime,
dedicated to the pursuit of happiness or to the protection
of property ever satisfy the deepest longings of the human
soul? Can a regime,
devoted to the rational accumulation of property answer
those higher order needs or higher order virtues,
like honor, nobility and sacrifice?
Can a regime, devoted to the avoidance of
pain, discomfort and anxiety, produce anything more than
contemporary forms of Epicureanism and Nihilism?
In any case, I'm suggesting no more than any
other land could America insulate itself from the great
heights as well as the great depths of later forms of
modernity. America, as a former teacher of
mine once said, is the land where the many
facets, the many faces of modernity are working themselves
out. We are but a moment in the kind
of comprehensive self-dissatisfaction that is
modernity so that a return to Lockeanism,
in many ways, is not so much a cure for the
pathologies of modernity. I would suggest that those
pathologies are themselves already rooted in the
pathologies of Locke. I will end on that sober note
and encourage you to take Rousseau's advice about loving
one's country seriously on Tuesday.